Morality for Humans (Record no. 84841)
[ view plain ]
000 -LEADER | |
---|---|
fixed length control field | 02496nam a22001817a 4500 |
008 - FIXED-LENGTH DATA ELEMENTS--GENERAL INFORMATION | |
fixed length control field | 160718b xxu||||| |||| 00| 0 eng d |
020 ## - INTERNATIONAL STANDARD BOOK NUMBER | |
International Standard Book Number | 9780226324944 |
082 ## - DEWEY DECIMAL CLASSIFICATION NUMBER | |
Classification number | 171.7 |
Cutter | Joh |
100 ## - MAIN ENTRY--PERSONAL NAME | |
Personal name | Johnson, Mark |
245 ## - TITLE STATEMENT | |
Title | Morality for Humans |
Remainder of title | : Ethical Understanding from the Perspective of Cognitive Science |
260 ## - PUBLICATION, DISTRIBUTION, ETC. (IMPRINT) | |
Place of publication, distribution, etc | Chicago |
Name of publisher, distributor, etc | The University of Chicago Press |
Date of publication, distribution, etc | 2014 |
300 ## - PHYSICAL DESCRIPTION | |
Number of Pages | xii, 261p. |
Dimensions | 9x6 |
520 ## - Remark | |
Summary, etc | What is the difference between right and wrong? This is no easy question to answer, yet we constantly try to make it so, frequently appealing to some hidden cache of cut-and-dried absolutes, whether drawn from God, universal reason, or societal authority. Combining cognitive science with a pragmatist philosophical framework in Morality for Humans: Ethical Understanding from the Perspective of Cognitive Science, Mark Johnson argues that appealing solely to absolute principles and values is not only scientifically unsound but even morally suspect. He shows that the standards for the kinds of people we should be and how we should treat one another-which we often think of as universal-are in fact frequently subject to change. And we should be okay with that. Taking context into consideration, he offers a remarkably nuanced, naturalistic view of ethics that sees us creatively adapt our standards according to given needs, emerging problems, and social interactions. Ethical naturalism is not just a revamped form of relativism. Indeed, Johnson attempts to overcome the absolutist-versus-relativist impasse that has been one of the most intractable problems in the history of philosophy. He does so through a careful and inclusive look at the many ways we reason about right and wrong. Much of our moral thought, he shows, is automatic and intuitive, gut feelings that we follow up and attempt to justify with rational analysis and argument. However, good moral deliberation is not limited merely to intuitive judgments supported after the fact by reasoning. Johnson points out a crucial third element: we imagine how our decisions will play out, how we or the world would change with each action we might take. Plumbing this imaginative dimension of moral reasoning, he provides a psychologically sophisticated view of moral problem solving, one perfectly suited for the embodied, culturally embedded, and ever-developing human creatures that we are. |
546 ## - LANGUAGE NOTE | |
Language note | ENG |
650 ## - SUBJECT ADDED ENTRY--TOPICAL TERM | |
Topical term or geographic name as entry element | Ethics |
Topical term or geographic name as entry element | Cognitive science- Moral and ethical aspects |
942 ## - ADDED ENTRY ELEMENTS (KOHA) | |
Item type | Book |
Withdrawn status | Lost status | Damaged status | Not for loan | Collection code | Permanent location | Current location | Shelving location | Date acquired | Full call number | Barcode | Date last seen | Koha item type |
---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|---|
Book | HBCSE | HBCSE | Psychology | 2016-07-18 | 171.7 Joh | 23306 | 2016-07-18 | Book |